Its use, I. 466, § 7
Its imperfections, II. 6, § 1 Double use, ibid.
The use of language destroyed by the subtilty of disputing, II. 25-6, 6, 7, 8 Ends of language, II. 37, § 23 Its imperfections, not easy to be cured, II. 42, 2: II. 43-4, § 4, 5, 6
The cure of them necessary to philosophy, II. 43, § 3 To use no word without a clear and distinct idea annexed to it, is one remedy of the imperfec- tions of language, II. 46, 58,9 Propriety in the use of words, another remedy, II. 47, § 11 Law of nature generally allowed, I. 37, § 6
There is, though not innate, I, 43,13
Its inforcement, I. 371, § 6 Learning, the ill state of learning in
these latter ages, II. 6, &c. Of the schools lies chiefly in the abuse of words, II. 11, &c.
II. 25 Such learning of ill consequence, II. 27, § 10, &c. Liber, what, I. 224-7, § 8, 9,
To, 11, 12: I. 228, § 15 Belongs not to the will, I, 227,
14 To be determined by the result of our own deliberation, is no restraint of liberty, I. 250, § 48, 49, 50 Founded in a power of suspend- ing our particular desires,, I. 249, 47: I. 252-3, $51,52 Light, its absurd definitions, I 456, § 10
ADNESS, I. 140, § 13. Op- position to reason deserves that name, I. 419, § 4 Magisterial, the most knowing are least magisterial, II. 232, § 4 Making, I. 322, 2 Man not the product of blind chance, I. 189, § 6
The essence of man is placed in his shape, II. 136, § 16. We know not his real essence, I. 475, 3: I. 487, § 22: I. 491, The boundaries of the human species not determined, I. 491, § 27
What makes the same individual
man, I. 342, 21: I. 347,929 The same man may be different persons, I. 341, § 19 Mathematics, their methods, II. 213, 7. Improvement, II. 219, $15 Matter incomprehensible, both in its cohesion and divisibility, I. 303, 23: I. 309, § 30, 31 What, II. 30, 15 Whether it may think, is not to be known, II. 80-103, § 6: II. 88, &c. Cannot produce motion, or any thing elfe, II. 192, § 10 And motion cannot produce thought, ibid.
Not eternal, II, 197, § 18 Maxims, II. 157, &c.: II. 171-3, $ 12, 13, 14, 15
Not alone selfevident, II.158,53 Are not the truths first known, II. 162, § 9
Not the foundation of our know, ledge, II., 163,
Wherein their evidence consists, II. 164, § 10 Their use, 11. 165-71, 11, 12 Why the most general self-evi- dent propositions alone, pass for maxims, II. 171, § 11 Are commonly proofs, only where there is no need of proofs, II. 173, § 15 Of little use, with clear terms, II. 175, § 19
Of dangerous use, with doubtful terms, II. 171, &c. § 12: II. 176, 20
When firft known, 1. 17, &c.
§ 9, 12, 13: I. 19, § 14: 1. 21, 16
How they gain assent, I. 25-6,
Made from particular observa- tions, ibid.
Not in the understanding before they are actually known, I. 2622
Neither their terms nor ideas
innate, I. 27, 23 Least known to children and il- literate people, I. 30, § 27 Memory, 1. 128, § 2 Attention, pleasure, and pain, settle ideas in the memory, I. 129, § 3
And repetition, ibid, § 4: I. 131,6
Difference of memory, 1. 129- 30, 4, 5
In remembrance, the mind some- times active, sometimes pas- sive, 1. 131, 7
Its necessity, I. 130, § 5: I. 132,8
Defects, 1. 132, § 8, 9 In brutes, 1. 133, 10 Metaphysics, and school divinity filled with uninstructive pro- positions, II. 184, 9 Method used in mathematics, II. 213,87
Mind, the quickness of its actions, I. 125, § 10
Minutes, hours, days, not necessary to duration, I. 174, § 23
Miracles, the ground of assent to miracles, II. 239, § 13 Misery, what, I. 245, § 42 Modes, mixed, I. 274, § I Made by the mind, I. 275, 2 Sometimes got by the explication of their names, 1. 276, § 3 Whence a mixed mode has its unity, ibid, § 4
Occasionof mixed modes, I. 277, $5
Mixed modes, their ideas, how got, I. 278, 9 Modes simple and complex, I. 145,5
Simple modes, 1. 147, § 1 Of motion, I. 209, § 2 Moral good and evil, what, 1. 370, $5
Three rules, whereby men judge
of moral rectitude, I. 371, § 7 Beings, how founded on simple ideas of sensation and reflec. tion, I. 377-9, § 14, 15 Rules not self-evident, I. 35, § 4 Variety of opinions, concerning moral rules, whence, I. 36, $5,6
Rules, if innate, cannot with
public allowance be transgres- sed, I. 40, &c. 11, 12, 13 Morality, capable of demonstra. tion, II. 250, 16: II.112, 18: II. 214, § 8 The proper study of mankind, TI. 216, § 11
Of actions, in their conformity to a rule, I. 379, § 15 Mistakes in moral notions, owing to names, ibid. § 16 Discourses in morality, if not clear, it is the fault of the speaker, II. 51, § 17 Hindrances of demonstrative treating of morality. 1. Want of marks. 2. Complexedness, II. 113, § 19. 3. Interest, II. 115, § 20
Change of names in morality, changes not the nature of things, TT. 130, $9
And mechanism, hard to be re- conciled, I. 45, § 14 Secured amidst men's wrong judgments, 1. 268, § 70 Motion, slow or very swift, why not perceived, I. 166-7, § 7, 8, 9, 10, 11
Voluntary, inexplicable, II. 198, $19
Its absurd definitions, I. 455-6, $ 8,9
AMING of ideas, I. 138, § 8 Names, moral established by law, are not to be varied from, II. 132, § 10
Of substances, standing for real essences, are not capable to convey certainty to the un. derstanding, II. 146, § 5 Standing for nominal essences, will make some, though not many certain propositions, II. 147, § 6 Why men substitute names for real essences, which they know not, II. 33, § 19 Two false suppositions, in such an use of names, II. 35, § 21 A particular name to every par- ticular thing impossible, 1. 435, § 2
And useless, ibid. § 3 Proper names, where used, I. 436, § 4, 5
Specific names are affixed to the nominal essence, I. 450, § 16 Of simple ideas and substances, refer to things, I. 453, § 2 What names stand for both real and nominal essence, 1.454, $3 Of simple ideas not capable of definitions, ibid. § 4 Why, I. 455,7
Of least doubtful signification, I. 460, § 15
Have few ascents "in linea dicamentali," I. 461, § 16 Of complex ideas, may be defin ed, Í. 459, § 12 VOL. II.
Of mixed modes stand for arbi- trary ideas, I. 463, § 2, 3: I. 504, § 44
Tie together the parts of their complex ideas, I. 468, § 10- Stand always for the real essence, I. 471, § IA
Why got, usually, before the ideas are known, ibid. § 15 Of relations comprehended under those of mixed modes, I. 472, $16
General names of substances stand for sorts, I. 473, § I Necessary to species, I. 501, § 39 Proper names belong only to sub- stances, I. 503, § 42
Of modes in their first applica- tion, I. 504-5, § 44, 45 Of substances in their first appli- cation, I. 506-7, § 46, 47 Specific names stand for different things in different men, I. 508, § 48
Are put in the place of the thing supposed to have the real es- sence of the species, ibid. § 49 Of mixed modes, doubtful often, because of the great composi- tion of the ideas they stand for, II. 8, 6 Because they want standards in nature, II. 9, § 7
Of substances, doubtful, because referred to patterns, that can- not be known, or known but imperfectly, II, 12, &c, § 11, 12, 13, 14
In their philosophical use hard to have settled significations, II, 15, 15 Instance, liquor, II. 16, § 16: gold, II. 17, § 17: II. 302, $17 Ofsimple ideas, why least doubt. ful, II. 18, 18 Least compounded ideas have the least dubious names, H.
Yet very useful, II. 217, § 12 How to be improved, ibid. What has hindered its improve- ment, II. 218, § 12 Necessity, 1. 227, § 13 Negative terms, I. 428, § 4 Names, signify the absence of positive ideas, I. 111, § 5 Newton (Mr.) II. 166, § 11 Nothing: that nothing cannot pro- duce any thing, is demonstra- tion, II. 188, § 3 Notions, I. 275, § 2 Number, I. 189.
Modes of number the most dis- tinct ideas, ibid. § 3 Demonstrations in numbers, the most determinate, I. 190, § 4 The general measure, I. 193, 68 Affords the clearest idea of infi- nity, I. 200, 9 Numeration, what, I. 190, § 5 Names, necessary to it, ibid. $5,6
And order, I. 192, § 7 Why not early in children, and in some never, ibid.
OBSCURITY, unavoidable in
ancient authors, II. 12, § 10 The cause of it, in our ideas, I. 384, § 3 Obstinate, they are most, who have least examined, II. 230, § 3 Opinion, what, II. 226, 3 How opinions grow up to prin- ciples, I. 50, &c. § 22, 23, 24, 25, 26
Of others, a wrong ground of as-
sent, II. 228,6: II. 294, §17 Organs our organs suited to our state, I. 296, &c. § 12, 13
Holds a rational discourse, ibid. Particles join parts, or whole sen-
tences together, II. 1, § 1 In them lies the beauty of well, speaking, ibid. § 2 How their use is to be known, II. 2, § 3
They express some action, or pos- ture of the mind, ibid. § 4 Pascal, his great memory, I. 133, § 9
Passion, I. 281, § 11 Passions, how they lead us into errour, II. 237, § 11
Turn on pleasure and pain, 1. 216, 3
Passions are seldom single, 1. 243,39 Perception threefold, I. 223, § 5 In perception, the mind for the
most part passive, I. 121, §1 Is an impression made on the mind, ibid. § 3, 4 In the womb, I. 122, 5 Difference between it, and innate ideas, ibid. 6
Puts the difference between the animal and vegetable king- dom, I. 126,
The several degrees of it, show the wisdom and goodness of the maker, ibid. 12. Belongs to all animals,ibid. § 12,
13, 14. The first inlet of knowledge, I. 127, § 15
Person, what, I. 333, §9
A forensic term, I. 346, § 26 The same consciousness alone makes the same person, I. 336, § 13: I. 343, § 23 The same soul without the same consciousness, makes not the same person, I. 337, § 14, &c. Reward and punishment follow personal identity, I. 340, § 18 Phancy, I. 132, 8 Phantastical ideas, I. 393, § I Place, I. 49-50, § 7, 8 Use of place, I. 150, § 9 Nothing but a relative position, I. 151, § 19 Some.
Sometimes taken for the space a body fills, I. 152, § 10 Twofold, I. 182, § 6: I. 183, $6,7
Fleasure and pain, 1. 215, § 1: I. 219, § 15, 16
Join themselves to most of our ideas, I. 105, § 2 Pleasure, why joined to several ac- tions, I. 105, § 3 Fower, how we come by its idea, I. 220, § I
Active and passive, I. 221, § 2 No passive power in God, no active power in matter; both active and passive in spirits, Ibid. § ż
Our idea of active power clearest from reflection, ibid. § 4 Powers operate not on powers, I. 230, § 18 Make a a great part of the ideas of substances, I. 293, § 7 Why, I. 294, § 8
An idea of sensation and reflec-
tion, I. 111, § 8 Practical principles not innate, I. 33, § 1
Not universally assented to, I. 34, § 2
Are for operation, ibid. § 3 Not agreed, I. 44, § 14 Different, I. 50, § 21
Principles, not to be received with- out strict examination, II. 211, § 4: II. 287, § 8 The ill consequences of wrong principles, II. 288, &c. § 9, 10 None innate, I. 13 None universally assented to, I. 14, § 2, 3, 4
How ordinarily got, I. 50, § 22,
Grounds of probability in specu lation, II. 237, § 12 Wrong measures of probability, II. 287, § 7
How evaded by prejudiced minds, II. 291-2, § 13, 14 Proofs, II. 71, §3 Properties of specific essences, not known, I. 485, § 19
Of things very numerous, I. 405, 10: I. 417,
Propositions, identical, teach no- thing, II. 177, § 2
Generical, teach nothing, II. 180, 4: II. 185, § 13 Wherein a part of the definition is predicated of the subject, teach nothing, II. 180-1, § 5, 6
But the signification of the word, II. 182, § 7 Concerning substances, generally either trifling or uncertain, II. 183,9
Merely verbal, how to be known II. 185, § 12
Abstract terms, predicated one of another, produce merely verbal propositions, ibid. Or part of a complex idea, pre- dicated of the whole, II. 180, § 4: II. 185, § 13 More propositions, merely ver bal, than is suspected, II. 185, $13 Universal propositions concern not existence, II. 186, § 1 What propositions concern exist ence, ibid. Certain propositions, concerning existence are particular; con- cerning abstract ideas, may be general, II. 207, § 13 Mental, II. 139, §3: II. 140, $5 140,$5 Verbal, ibid. 3: ibid. § 5 Mental, hard to be treated, II. 139, § 3, 4
« ForrigeFortsæt » |